Listing 1 - 10 of 10 |
Sort by
|
Choose an application
Phenomenology --- Transcendence (Philosophy) --- Phénoménologie --- Transcendance (Philosophie) --- Phénoménologie
Choose an application
Phänomenologie und Philosophische Anthropologie stehen seit jeher in einem schwierigen Verhältenis. Zwar bestehen zwischen den Denkrichtungen personelle, zeitliche und bis zu einem gewissen Grade auch inhaltlich enge Beziehungen, dennoch verbleibt die Phänomenologie gegenüber der Philosophischen Anthropologie in einer distanzierten und kritische Haltung. Obgleich die Philosophische Anthropologie aus Sicht mancher Vertreter der phänomenologischen Methode diametral gegenüberzustehen scheint, lässt sich dennoch ein beständiges Spannungsverhältnis, und bei manchen r Vertreter der Phänomenologie sogar die Möglichkeit zu einer phänomenologisch-philosophischen Anthropologie sehen. Die Intention des vorliegenden Bandes Besteht darin, dieses schwierige Verhältnis zwischen Phänomenologie und Philosophischer Anthropologie näher in der Blick zu nehmen. Dabei ist es ein Anliegen, den vielen anthropoligischen Thesenbildungen nicht überdies noch eine phänomenologische beizustellen, sondern kritisch zu überprüfen, ob sich die Frage der Philosophischen Anthropologie aus Perspektive der Phänomenologie sinnvoll stellen lässt.
Choose an application
This edited collection explores the problem of violence from the vantage point of meaning. Taking up the ambiguity of the word ‘meaning’, the chapters analyse the manner in which violence affects and in some cases constitutes the meaningful structure of our lifeworld, on individual, social, religious and conceptual levels. The relationship between violence and meaning is multifaceted, and is thus investigated from a variety of different perspectives within the continental tradition of philosophy, including phenomenology, post-structuralism, critical theory and psychoanalysis. Divided into four parts, the volume explores diverging meanings of the concept of violence, as well as transcendent or religious violence- a form of violence that takes place between humanity and the divine world. Going on to investigate instances of immanent and secular violence, which occur at the level of the group, community or society, the book concludes with an exploration of violence and meaning on the individual level: violence at the level of the self, or between particular persons. With its focus on the manifold of relations between violence and meaning, as well as its four part focus on conceptual, transcendent, immanent and individual violence, the book is both multi-directional and multi-layered.
Violence --- Philosophy. --- Social sciences—Philosophy. --- Ethics. --- Political philosophy. --- Phenomenology . --- Social Philosophy. --- Moral Philosophy. --- Political Philosophy. --- Phenomenology. --- Philosophy, Modern --- Political philosophy --- Deontology --- Ethics, Primitive --- Ethology --- Moral philosophy --- Morality --- Morals --- Philosophy, Moral --- Science, Moral --- Philosophy --- Values --- Social sciences --- Political science --- Moral Philosophy and Applied Ethics. --- Social philosophy --- Social theory
Choose an application
Choose an application
Choose an application
This paper provides a new way of supporting Edith Stein’s critique that Martin Heidegger prematurely forecloses the question of eternal being, through a reinterpretation of Heidegger’s conceptualization of the relationship between theology and philosophy. Heidegger argues throughout his middle-period works (1924 -1930) that the traditional concept of eternity is a derivative and inauthentic modification of primordial, finite temporality. While it is commonly accepted that Heidegger rejects the position that eternity occupies within traditional ontology, a number of contemporary Heidegger scholars interpret Heidegger’s ontology to be compatible with faith beliefs in God’s eternity, and more broadly, with theology. I argue, to the contrary, that there is an irresolvable antagonism between theology and Heidegger’s conception of ontology. While an understanding of being that is compatible with faith beliefs in God’s eternity must be open to the possible mystery of being, Heidegger disregards the possibility that the meaning of being may lie outside the grasp of, in his words, “purely self-reliant Dasein”. This ultimately supports Stein’s critique of Heidegger’s concept of finitude. Namely, while Heidegger attempts to think the finitude of Dasein, without a presupposed infinitude, the meaning of finitude cannot be unfastened from the idea of the infinite, which delimits the finite being as finite in the first place.
Choose an application
Heidegger possessed a language of crisis and danger throughout his career which he never relinquished. He suspected that the western world was descending into nihilism, and that hope for philosophy and the sciences was threatened in their essences. The source of this threat in his view was modern technology, seen as the consummation of the history of metaphysics. At one level, Heidegger’s thinking is representative of many contemporaries in German interwar conservative and reactionary circles. Yet Heidegger’s notion of modern technology was especially shaped by the works of Ernst Jünger. Their relationship, and the relationship of their ideas can illuminate what Heidegger had in mind when he questioned technology, and the vision he had both of history and of the future. Despite the broad insights they share, Jünger and Heidegger however, end up with significantly different dispositions; whereas, the former exalts in technology and the age it brought about, Heidegger expressed fear and apprehension. This paper will seek to explain Jünger and Heidegger’s respective approaches to technology and history, and furthermore identify the precise points of resonance between them. It shall follow their vision in order to understand why Heidegger concluded that Jünger’s reading of history and technology was not only incorrect, but dangerous.
Choose an application
Can we voluntarily reform ourselves? In Being and Nothingness, Sartre rejects this possibility. For him, all attempts at voluntary self-reform are in “bad faith”. In this thesis, I argue that Sartre’s rejection is incompatible with several aspects of his theory. To do this, I first trace Sartre’s arguments for the rejection of voluntary self-reform back to the theory of motivation and to their ontological foundations. For Sartre, the motive is a non-being. Since the in-itself is full and solid of being, it cannot be the condition of possibility for the motive. This leads him to the for-itself. The for-itself is responsible for the motive in two ways: it is the conditions of possibilities for “there to be” a world and for the world to have a meaning. As the ontological foundation for meaning, the for-itself chooses its fundamental project via ontological freedom and maintains this choice by determining particular projects. Following these ontological arguments, Sartre moves onto the rejection of voluntary self-reform. Voluntary self-reform is a particular project. In addition, it requires the recognition of the fundamental project. However, recognition implies the nihilation of the thing recognized. Since the for-itself chooses particular projects in accordance with the fundamental project, a genuine voluntary self-reform is impossible. In my opinion, Sartre’s rejection contradicts with three elements of his work, namely his positions on self-determination, radical conversion and existential psychoanalysis. First, I argue that the alignment between the particular project and the fundamental project implies that once the for-itself chooses its fundamental project, it cannot change this choice. Second, I attempt to show that radical conversion requires the nihilation of recognition. This nihilation implies two paradoxes: the for-itself must choose without values, and it must nihilate itself without recognizing itself. Third, I suggest that existential psychoanalysis requires the open possibility for recognition. In the final section, I propose lifting Sartre’s ban on voluntary self-reform would make Being and Nothingness more consistent.
Choose an application
The present text discusses the phenomenon of death and its impact on the self-understanding of the human being. I try to show that Levinas’ reflections on death can be read as a viable alternative to Heidgger’s approach to the same topic. Heidegger’s analysis of death reveals the irreplaceable character of Dasein and the responsibility that Dasein has towards itself. However, it meets its limits when confronted by questions relating to the death of the other human being. In Heidegger the death of the other does not become relevant in the problem of Dasein’s authenticity. In contrast to Heidegger, Levinas puts the death of the other in the center of his thinking. More precisely, he states that the death of the fellow human being is a source of passivity and affectivity; like the manifestation of the other as face, death reveals the intersubjective character of human existence. For Levinas, the death or dying of the other inspires awareness of our responsibility. I also argue that Levinasian thought finds application in concrete life situations, such as those that involve dementia care. Like the encounter with the face of the other, the vulnerability of demented people provokes an experience of pure passivity and affectivity. Interdependency and human suffering are not marks of weakness, but are fundamental characteristics of human existence: they point to our basic responsibility for the other.
Choose an application
Listing 1 - 10 of 10 |
Sort by
|